The Quantum Thomist

Musings about quantum physics, classical philosophy, and the connection between the two.
Aristotelian Potentia and the measurement problem.


Are fundamental particles of matter indestructible?
Last modified on Sat Jul 13 18:38:44 2019


Suppose that we wanted to ask what the most famous equation in physics is. There are, I imagine, a few candidates.

But ask a random person on the street to name an equation from physics, and if I were a gambling man (which I am not) I would be willing to bet that the majority of them would say E = mc2, even if they don’t understand what the equation means. So what does it mean?

First of all, we need to ask what the symbols mean. E represents energy, m represents mass and c the speed of light. Well, that’s simple enough. It means that mass and energy are equivalent, doesn’t it?

Well, no it doesn’t. In this post, I intend to briefly show where Einstein's equation comes from, and by doing so take a look at some aspects of its significance.

Before we begin, we need to ask what the speed of light, mass and energy and mass represent in classical physics.

The speed of light is the speed at which light travels in a vacuum. Simple enough. It is also linked to the strength of the electric and magnetic forces. It plays a particularly important role in special relativity. The Lorentz transformations which are used to convert the co-ordinates in one invariant reference frame to another are dependent on the relative velocity divided by the speed of light. In this way, the speed of light is a natural way to convert between durations in time and distances (which we need to do when considering what the path of a particle is as observed by someone moving at a constant velocity to ourselves).

Mass is an inherent property of matter that does two jobs:

  1. It represents the resistance of an object to accelerating (Newton’s second law is the definition of this sense of mass).
  2. The gravitational force between two objects is proportional to the product of their masses (Newton’s law of gravity). It measures both the strength of the gravitational field generated by the object, and the object’s response to a gravitational field generated by something else.

You might ask why the mass plays two seemingly independent roles in classical physics: and if you do ask that, think about it in the right way, and know enough about geometry, then you are well on the way to uncovering the general theory of relativity. But I digress.

Energy is a bit different. In Newtonian mechanics, energy is basically something that you get by throwing together various numbers. It’s main use is that it is a conserved quantity. Newton’s second and third laws together mean that the total energy does not change in time. Energy is transferred from one object to another, but the sum of the energy remains the same. In fact, it is often easier to deduce the dynamics of a collision by using the conservation of energy and momentum than it is to explicitly solve Newton’s equations.

Before giving the equation for the energy, I need a couple of other definitions. Firstly, we have the momentum, p, which is mass times velocity. This features in Newton’s second and third equations; Newton’s third equation states that momentum is also a conserved quantity. Next, the electrostatic potential, which I will write as cA0. The electric force is the rate of change of the potential with respect to distance. Then we have the magnetic potential, A, which can be used to compute the force from magnetism.

Newton’s equation for the energy for a single particle of electric charge q in an electromagnetic field (excluding gravity and the other forces: gravity doesn’t affect the conclusions of argument but makes it considerably more complicated if we want to do gravity in a manner consistent with relativity; the other forces arise as a result of quantum physics and we are here discussing classical physics) is then

    (p---qA-)2
E =    2m    + qcA0

The first term is known as the kinetic energy, and the second the potential energy. Because energy is conserved, we can increase the kinetic energy (make the particle go faster) by reducing the potential energy, or we can make the particle slower and increase the potential energy, but the sum of the two terms must remain constant. If we have more than one particle, we can add together their individual energies, and can transfer kinetic or potential energy from one particle to another, but the total energy must remain constant.

Einstein realised that this equation was inconsistent with Maxwell’s equations for electromagnetism. Newton’s equation for the energy is wrong. Einstein also worked out what the right equation is, and it is usually expressed as (in a form that makes clear the symmetry between energy and momentum)

         2          2 2    24
(E - qcA0) = (p - qA) c + m c .

We can rearrange it to give,

    ∘ -----------------
E =   (p- qA )2c2 + m2c4 + qcA0.

So once again, we seem to have two terms: the potential energy, and something else. We can transfer energy from the something else to the potential energy and vice versa, and from one particle to another, but again energy is conserved. The potential energy has exactly the same form as in Newton’s formula, but the other term is a bit different from Newton’s formula to the Kinetic energy.

To find the connection between Einstein’s and the Newtonian expressions, we need to do a little bit of algebra. First of all, we re-arrange it

       ∘ ---(p---qA)2c2
E = mc2  1+ -----2-4---+ qcA0.
               m  c

Then we do a low momentum expansion,

         [                                    ]
E = mc2 +  (p---qA)2-- (p--qA-)4-+ (p--qA-)6+ ... + qcA
             2m        8m3c2      16m5c4             0

So we have three terms: the potential energy; one which depends on the momentum, and whose most significant contribution when the momentum is much smaller than the mass times the speed of light is the Newtonian kinetic energy (the remaining contributions are much smaller than the experimental precision of the observations that were used to support Newton's formula; but have subsequently been verified by more precise experiments); and a third term, the familiar mc2, which is entirely absent in Newtonian mechanics. Since in Newtonian mechanics all that matters is energy difference rather than the absolute energy, no pre-twentieth century experiment was affected by its presence.

What this equation tells us is that mass is a type of energy. It is not equivalent to energy, because it is not the only type of energy (no more than potential energy is equivalent to energy as a whole). It also suggests that, just as we convert potential energy into kinetic energy and vice versa, so we can also convert kinetic energy into mass and vice versa. (One might also think that one can convert potential energy into mass; but when we get into relativistic quantum physics, the electromagnetic potential is regarded in a different way, so this becomes a bit more complicated. For this discussion, I’ll just consider the conversion between kinetic energy and mass.)

But this last point is troubling philosophically, at least for certain philosophies, most especially that adopted by Newton. Mass is an intrinsic property of matter. To create new mass means creating new matter. For example, each electron has the same mass; the only way we can convert kinetic energy into electron mass is to create new electrons. This suggests that it is possible to create (and destroy) matter.

But in the mechanical philosophy – both classical mechanics and quantum mechanics – the fundamental type of matter, the corpuscles, are supposed to be indestructible (and, the current best theory suggests that electrons are elementary; though even if they are composite the same considerations would apply to whatever electrons are made of). This is one of the primary axioms of mechanism. The mechanical philosophy supposes that physics reduces to the different locomotions and arrangements of corpuscles; and has no capacity to appreciate their creation and destruction. Neither Newton’s equations of motion nor Schrödinger’s equation can describe the creation or destruction of matter.

Now, we could perhaps rescue mechanism by saying that conversion between kinetic and mass energy never occurs in practice; there is nothing in Einstein’s equation saying that mandates that it must happen. It just suggests that it might be possible. The only requirement of the equation is that mass energy plus kinetic energy plus potential energy remains constant. Unfortunately, experiment now intervenes and tells us that kinetic energy is indeed converted into new particles. So the natural implication of Einstein’s equation was right, and the original versions of the mechanical philosophy were wrong.

Interestingly, though, Aristotle was quite happy with one form of matter being converted into another; for example when wood burns and becomes fire. This example is, of course, taken from Greek physics, which we know is problematic. But even if the reasons why Aristotle thought that his philosophy was necessary were false, it does not mean that his philosophy was in fact false. It just means that the arguments he used to support it were bad. One can defend a good idea through bad argumentation. Aristotle's philosophy becomes relevant again when we find a better example of what he was proposing; and thus his conclusion that the correct metaphysics must be general enough to admit to the possibility of transmutation from one type of matter to another. Modern physics comes to a similar conclusion: that one form of matter can emit, absorb or transform into another. The only requirement that Einstein left us with was that energy has to be conserved. New matter arises from the kinetic energy of something else. You cannot create from nothing, but only by taking from something else. Moreover, that something else has to have enough kinetic energy or momentum to compensate for the mass of the new particles; the effect has to be contained in some way within the cause. So find ourselves with two fundamental Aristotelian principles: the principle of causality (every actualised potential is caused by something already actual), and the principle of proportionate causality (an effect can only come about if the cause possessed the power to bring about that effect; i.e. the effect is allowed as a possibility by the inherent nature of the cause).

So what we need to do is construct a new physics that contains a mathematical description of material particles being created and destroyed and has the principles of causality and proportionate causality built in.



On physical determinism.


Reader Comments:



Post Comment:

Some html formatting is supported,such as <b> ... <b> for bold text , < em>... < /em> for italics, and <blockquote> ... </blockquote> for a quotation
All fields are optional
Comments are generally unmoderated, and only represent the views of the person who posted them.
I reserve the right to delete or edit spam messages, obsene language,or personal attacks.
However, that I do not delete such a message does not mean that I approve of the content.
It just means that I am a lazy little bugger who can't be bothered to police his own blog.
Weblinks are only published with moderator approval
Posts with links are only published with moderator approval (provide an email address to allow automatic approval)

Name:
Email:
Website:
Title:
Comment:
What is 1600-2?